Conventions |
$\dashv$ | Old reference |
Old version |
$\to$ | New version |
Old description |
$\to$ | New description |
Ch. 1 ; page 2 ; 3rd para. ; l. 2
|
The advantage of the language proposed herein is that it allows one
to describe weak equivalences [...]
|
$\to$ |
while the scope of the language developed herein is to allow the description of
weak equivalences [...]
|
Ch. 1 ; page 2 ; sec. 1.1.1.2 ; l. 5
|
in colimits of
|
$\to$ |
of colimits in
|
Ch. 1 ; page 3 ; sec. 1.1.1.3 ; l. -1
|
verfyi
|
$\to$ |
satisfy
|
Ch. 1 ; page 23 ; sec. 1.2.1.6 ; l. 1
|
Let $\Delta$ denote the simplex category whose objects are
finite ordinals and whose morphisms are order-preserving maps.
|
$\to$ |
Let $\Delta$ denote the simplex category whose objects are
non-zero finite ordinals and whose morphisms are order-preserving maps.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; after sec. 1.2.1.22
|
No existing section.
|
$\to$ |
1.2.1.23. Cones. Let $D$ be a small category and $\mathcal{C}$ be a category. Denote by $\Delta_D$ the functor $\mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{C}^D$ that maps every object $X$ of $\mathcal{C}$ to its associated constant functor $D \to \mathcal{C}$ mapping any object and arrow in $D$ to the object $X$ and identity on $X$, respectively. We shall speak of a cone in $\mathcal{C}$ over $D$ to refer to a natural transformation of the form $\Delta_D(X) \Rightarrow F$ where $X$ is an object in $\mathcal{C}$, which will be referred to as the peak, and $F$ is a functor from $D$ to $\mathcal{C}$.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; after sec. 1.2.1.22
|
No existing section.
|
$\to$ |
1.2.1.24. Cocones. Let $D$ be a small category, $\mathcal{C}$ be a category and denote by $\Delta_D$ the functor $\mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{C}^D$ defined in section 1.2.1.23. We shall speak of a cocone in $\mathcal{C}$ over $D$ to refer to a natural transformation of the form $F \Rightarrow \Delta_D(X)$ where $X$ is an object in $\mathcal{C}$, which will be referred to as the peak, and $F$ is a functor from $D$ to $\mathcal{C}$.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; after sec. 1.2.1.22
|
1.2.1.26. Diagrams. Let $\mathcal{C}$ be a small category [...]
|
$\to$ |
The numbering of the section is now 1.2.1.25 and Remark 1.17 has been added.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; sec. 1.2.1.23 / sec. 1.2.1.24
|
natural transformation
|
$\to$ |
cone / cocone
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; sec. 1.2.1.23 / sec. 1.2.1.24
|
No matching sentence.
|
$\to$ |
A cone / cocone such as $\alpha$ will later be said to be universal over its diagram $(D,F)$.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; sec. 1.2.1.27
|
A colimit sketch is a small category $\mathtt{S}$ equipped with a subset $Q$ of its diagrams that admits colimits in $\mathtt{S}$ such that for every object $x$ in $\mathtt{S}$, there exists a unique diagram of the form $(\mathbf{1},x)$ in $Q$. The diagrams and colimits in question will be said to be chosen. A model for a colimit sketch $\mathtt{S}$ in a category $\mathcal{C}$ is a functor $\mathtt{S} \to \mathcal{C}$ that preserves the chosen colimits in $\mathcal{C}$.
|
$\to$ |
A colimit sketch is a small category $\mathtt{S}$ equipped with a subset $Q$ of its universal cocones (see section 1.2.1.27) such that, for every object $x$ in $\mathtt{S}$, there exists a unique cocone in $Q$ defined over a diagram of the form $(\mathbf{1},x)$. The cocones in $Q$ as well as their associated diagrams and colimits (i.e. their peaks) will be said to be chosen. A model for a colimit sketch $\mathtt{S}$ in a category $\mathcal{C}$ is a functor $\mathtt{S} \to \mathcal{C}$ that sends the chosen cocones of $\mathtt{S}$ to universal cocones in $\mathcal{C}$.
|
Ch. 1 ; page 26 ; sec. 1.2.1.28
|
A limit sketch is a small category $\mathtt{S}$ equipped with a subset $Q$ of its diagrams that admits limits in $\mathtt{S}$ such that for every object $x$ in $\mathtt{S}$, there exists a unique diagram of the form $(\mathbf{1},x)$ in $Q$. The diagrams and limits in question will be said to be chosen. A model for a limit sketch $\mathtt{S}$ in a category $\mathcal{C}$ is a functor $\mathtt{S} \to \mathcal{C}$ that preserves the chosen limits in $\mathcal{C}$.
|
$\to$ |
A limit sketch is a small category $\mathtt{S}$ equipped with a subset $Q$ of its universal cones (see section 1.2.1.26) such that, for every object $x$ in $\mathtt{S}$, there exists a unique cone in $Q$ defined over a diagram of the form $(\mathbf{1},x)$. The cones in $Q$ as well as their associated diagrams and limits (i.e. their peaks) will be said to be chosen. A model for a limit sketch $\mathtt{S}$ in a category $\mathcal{C}$ is a functor $\mathtt{S} \to \mathcal{C}$ that sends the chosen cones of $\mathtt{S}$ to universal cones in $\mathcal{C}$.
|
Ch. 2 ; page 70 ; Rem 2.54 ; leftmost diagram
|
The dotted arrow goes from $\mathbb{S}_{\flat}$ to $\mathbb{S}_{\bullet}$
|
$\to$ |
The dotted arrow now goes from $\mathbb{S}_{\flat}$ to a point $\cdot$
|
Ch. 2 ; page 70 ; Rem 2.54 ; rightmost diagram ; bottom arrow
|
$\varkappa$
|
$\to$ |
$\varkappa \circ \varkappa_*$
|
Ch. 2 ; page 80 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. 6
|
where $\Delta$ is the category of finite ordinals and order-preserving maps between them.
|
$\to$ |
where $\Delta$ is the category of non-zero finite ordinals and order-preserving maps between them.
|
Ch. 2 ; page 80 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. 7
|
For every $n \in \omega$,
|
$\to$ |
For every non-zero ordinal $n \in \omega$,
|
Ch. 2 ; page 80 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. -5
|
First, consider the following leftmost canonical arrow from the initial object to the terminal object in $\mathbf{sSet}$.
|
$\to$ |
First, consider the canonical arrow given below, on the left, from the initial object to the terminal object in $\mathbf{sSet}$.
|
Ch. 2 ; page 81 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. 5
|
by replacing the canonical arrow $0 \to \mathbf{1}$ with
|
$\to$ |
by replacing the canonical arrow $\emptyset \to \mathbf{1}$ with
|
Ch. 2 ; page 81 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. 7 and l. 9
|
For every $n \in \omega$,
|
$\to$ |
For every non-zero $n \in \omega$,
|
Ch. 2 ; page 81 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; 3rd row of diagrams ; l. 15
|
$\mathbb{D}_2^{\flat}$ / $\beta_{\flat}$ / $\delta_2^{\flat}$ / $\beta_{*}$ / $\delta_1^{*}$
|
$\to$ |
$\mathbb{D}_1$ / $\beta_{*}$ / $\delta_2^{*}$ / $\beta$ / $\delta_1$
|
Ch. 2 ; page 82 ; sec. 2.4.2.4 ; l. 6
|
For every $n \in \omega$,
|
$\to$ |
For every non-zero $n \in \omega$,
|
Ch. 5 ; page 266 ; sec. 5.5.2.2 ; l. 2
|
By construction
|
$\to$ |
By definition
|
Ch. 5 ; page 266 ; sec. 5.5.2.2 ; l. 5
|
resulting from the factorisation of (5.42) generated with respect to the set of arrows $J_{\mathrm{cof}}$ is [...]
|
$\to$ |
that results from the leftmost factorisation of (5.42), which is generated with respect to the set of arrows $J_{\mathrm{cof}}$, is [...]
|
Ch. 5 ; page 266 ; sec. 5.5.2.2 ; item 2)
|
for every small category $\mathtt{T}$ and functor $\upvarphi$$:\mathtt{T} \to J_{\mathrm{cof}}$ that is compatible with the numbered category $(\mathcal{E}^D, \kappa)$, the image of any pushout of the colimit $\mathrm{col}_{\mathtt{T}}$$\upvarphi$ via the functor $\nabla_d:\mathcal{E}^D \to \mathcal{E}$ is a surtraction (resp. intraction) in $\hat{\mathcal{E}}_d$ for every object $d$ in $D$ (see implication, below).
|
$\to$ |
for every small category $\mathtt{T}$, functor $\upvarphi$$:\mathtt{T} \to J_{\mathrm{cof}}$ that is compatible with the numbered category $(\mathcal{E}^D, \kappa)$ and pushout arrow $p:X \to Y$ of the arrow $\mathrm{col}_{\mathtt{T}}$$\upvarphi$ (see the diagram below, on the left), the image of p via the functor $\nabla_d:\mathcal{E}^D \to \mathcal{E}$ is a surtraction (resp. intraction) in $\hat{\mathcal{E}}_d$ for every object $d$ in $D$.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 271 ; sec. 6.1 ; l. 6
|
reducing the length of these induction reasonings as [...]
|
$\to$ |
reducing the length of the different inductive definitions involved as [...]
|
Ch. 6 ; page 271 ; sec. 6.1 ; 6th para. ; l. 2
|
convergent conjugations
|
$\to$ |
convergent conjugation
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; l. 1
|
the definition of the $\omega$-globular and $\omega$-spinal sketches
|
$\to$ |
the definition of $\omega$-globular and $\omega$-spinal sketches
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; l. 14
|
for the generation of
|
$\to$ |
for the generating of
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; l. 17
|
by defining a natural set of vertebrae for coheroids and show that these generate a vertebral category when the coheroid contains certain parallel arrows;
$\to$ Reflexive spinal coheroids come along with reflexive vertebrae; $\to$ Magmoidal spinal coheroids come along with framing of vertebrae; |
$\to$ |
by equipping coheroids with sets of canonical vertebrae and show that these give rise to vertebral categories when the coheroids in question are endowed with certain parallel arrows. We shall come across two intermediate structures, namely:
$\to$ Reflexive spinal coheroids, which will come along with reflexive vertebrae; $\to$ Magmoidal spinal coheroids, which will come along with framing of vertebrae; |
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; 2nd par. ; l. 1
|
We introduce the kappa and tau constructions $\kappa_{1,k}^m$, $\kappa_{2,k}^m$ and $\tau_{1,k}^m(\beta)$, $\tau_{2,k}^m(\beta)$ linking globular sums of some dimension to those of lower dimension implied by their borders.
|
$\to$ |
We introduce the kappa and tau constructions $\kappa_{1,k}^m$, $\kappa_{2,k}^m$ and $\tau_{1,k}^m(\beta)$, $\tau_{2,k}^m(\beta)$ linking globular sums of some dimension to others of lower dimension.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; 2nd par. ; l. 3
|
Specifically, using the analogy between the notion of cell in an $\infty$-groupoid and that of topological discs, the kappa and tau constructions will link a gluing of discs of the form given below on the left to the gluing of discs as given on the right.
|
$\to$ |
Specifically, using the analogy between the notion of cell in an $\infty$-groupoid and the notion of topological discs, the kappa and tau constructions will link a gluing of discs of the form given below, on the left, to the gluing of lower dimensional discs given by their respective borders, as shown on the right.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; 2nd par. ; l. 6
|
The kappa constructions $\kappa_{1,k}^m$, $\kappa_{2,k}^m$ are to handle gluings as above where the middle discs are 'non-reversible' (e.g. for spinal seeds) while tau constructions $\tau_{1,k}^m(\beta)$, $\tau_{2,k}^m(\beta)$ are to handle gluings as above where the middle discs are 'reversible' (e.g. a node of spines whose head will help define the zoo of the spinal category).
|
$\to$ |
The kappa constructions $\kappa_{1,k}^m$, $\kappa_{2,k}^m$ are to handle gluings taking the form of whiskerings whose whiskers should be thought of as 'reversible' cells and whose middle parts should specifically be viewed as 'non-reversible' cells. This non-reversibility will concretely be charactirised by the use of seeds where we would most often use stems. For their part, tau constructions $\tau_{1,k}^m(\beta)$, $\tau_{2,k}^m(\beta)$ are to handle whiskerings whose cells should all be viewed as potentially 'reversible' cells.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; 2nd par. ; l. 12
|
$\to$ $(k,0)$-normal spinal coheroids come along with a morphism $\pi_k^0$ linking a 'non-reversible' disc of dimension $k$ to a gluing of a 'non-reversible' disc of dimension $k$ along two reversible ones of the same dimension and thus define a ternary composition of discs;
|
$\to$ |
$\to$ $(k,0)$-normal spinal coheroids come along with a morphism $\pi_k^0$ linking a 'non-reversible' cell of dimension $k$ to a gluing of a 'non-reversible' cell of dimension $k$ along two reversible ones of the same dimension and thus emulates a ternary composition of discs;
|
Ch. 6 ; page 272 ; 2nd par. ; l. 16
|
$\to$ $(k,1)$-normal spinal coheroids come along with a morphism $\pi_k^1$ linking a 'non-reversible' disc of dimension $k+1$ to a gluing of a 'non-reversible' disc of dimension $k+1$ along two reversible ones of dimension $k$ and thus define a ternary composition of discs. This notion depends on the construction $\pi_k^0$, which defines the composition of the borders.
|
$\to$ |
$\to$ $(k,1)$-normal spinal coheroids come along with a morphism $\pi_k^1$ linking a 'non-reversible' cell of dimension $k+1$ to a gluing of a 'non-reversible' cell of dimension $k+1$ along two reversible ones of dimension $k$ and thus emulates a ternary composition of discs. This notion will depend on the construction $\pi_k^0$, which will take care to compose the borders at dimension $k$.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; 2nd par. ; l. 4
|
Broadly, a $(k,m-k)$-transitive spinal coheroid is equipped with morphisms $\upsilon_k^{m-k}(\beta)$ encoding the compositions of 'reversible' discs of dimension $m$ along 'reversible' discs of dimesion $k$.
|
$\to$ |
Broadly, a $(k,m-k)$-transitive spinal coheroid is equipped with morphisms $\upsilon_k^{m-k}(\beta)$ encoding the compositions of 'reversible' cells of dimension $m$ along pairs of 'reversible' cells of dimension $k$.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; 2nd par. ; l. 7
|
The functoriality of these compositions will be ensured via the notion of closedness requiring the composition to be compatible with the spheres induced by the borders of the discs. Precisely, this requires the existence of the gluings of spheres along any pair of 'reversible' discs.
|
$\to$ |
The functoriality of these compositions will be ensured via the notion of closedness, which will require the compositions to be compatible with the spheres induced by the borders of the discs. Precisely, this requires the existence of gluings of spheres along any pair of 'reversible' cells.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; 2nd par. ; l. 11
|
Closedness will come along with canonical morphisms $d_{1,k}^m$, $d_{2,k}^m$, $\kappa_{k}^m$ and $\tau_{k}^m(\beta)$ that factorises the kappa and tau constructions in canonical ways.
|
$\to$ |
Closedness will come along with canonical morphisms $d_{1,k}^m$, $d_{2,k}^m$, $\kappa_{k}^m$ and $\tau_{k}^m(\beta)$ that factorises the kappa and tau constructions in canonical ways as follows.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; l.-19
|
These morphisms will help define the functoriality of our framings. Specifically, the functoriality will follow from the commutative diagrams constructed in section 6.3.3.2, called closedness and normality and section 6.3.3.3, called closedness and transitivity, via the canonical properties of the morphims $d_{1,k}^m$, $d_{2,k}^m$, $\kappa_{k}^m$ and $\tau_{k}^m(\beta)$ as follows:
- diagrams (6.30), (6.34) and (6.39) of section 6.3.3.2 will define the compatibility from the compositions of non-reversible discs to the compositions of spheres; - diagrams (6.32), (6.33) and (6.38) of section 6.3.3.2 will define the compatibility from the compositions of spheres to the compositions of non-reversible discs; - diagrams (6.40) and (6.41) of section 6.3.3.3 will define the compatibility from the compositions of reversible discs to the compositions of spheres; |
$\to$ |
These morphisms will help define the functoriality of our framings, which will specifically follow from the commutative diagrams constructed in section 6.3.3.2, called closedness and normality, and section 6.3.3.3, called closedness and transitivity. Because the inductive developments given in these sections are quite cumbersome, I would now like to specify these commutative diagrams as well as give a short description of their roles (see below) -- the reader is therefore excepted to come back here if they lose their way while reading these sections. Now, to resume our discussion, this so-called functoriality will follow from the canonical properties of the morphisms $d_{1,k}^m$, $d_{2,k}^m$, $\kappa_{k}^m$ and $\tau_{k}^m(\beta)$ as follows:
$\triangleright$ diagrams (6.30); (6.34) and (6.39) of section 6.3.3.2 will be used to ensure the functoriality of the whiskerings of non-reversible cells along pairs of reversible cells relative to the whiskerings of the spheres, induced by the borders of the previous non-reversible cells, along the same pairs of reversible cells; $\triangleright$ diagrams (6.32) and (6.38) of section 6.3.3.2, or, in fact, their lower parts, will be used to ensure the functoriality of the whiskerings of the spheres along pairs of reversible cells relative to the whiskerings of the non-reversible borders of these spheres along the same pairs of reversible cells; $\triangleright$ diagrams (6.40) and (6.41) of section 6.3.3.3 will be used to ensure the functoriality of the whiskerings of reversible cells relative to the whiskerings of the spheres, induced by the borders of the middle cells, along the same pair of reversible cells; $\triangleright$ all the other diagrams may be viewed as intermediate steps for the purpose of defining the functoriality of our framings. |
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; l.-9
|
We then finish the section by giving a summary of all the preceding constructions in the form of propositions explicitly exposing the framings of spines involved and their functoriality.
|
$\to$ |
We then finish the section by summarising the aformentioned constructions in the form of propositions expliciting the desired framings of spines and their functoriality.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 273 ; l.-6
|
These reflections give a 'reversible' structure to all our vertebrae and thereby allow us to define conjugations of spines.
|
$\to$ |
These reflections give a 'reversible' structure to the stems of our vertebrae and thereby allow us to define conjugations of spines.
|
Ch. 6 ; page 290 ; sec. 6.3.2 ; from l. 1 to l. -1
|
This section defines natural contexts in which one may see the kappa and tau constructions -- which one would like think of as mapping cylinders -- as actual cells or discs. In terms of intuition, these should therefore be understood as some sorts of compositions. On the one hand, normal spinal coheroids will permit the composition of
cylinders whose 'bases' are non-invertible cells but whose sides are (the composition being realised by the factorisations of the parallel pairs therefore), while, on the other hand, transitive spinal coheroids will permit the composition of cylinders whose 'bases' and sides are all invertible (the composition being realised by the factorisations of the parallel pairs therefore).
The term normal refers to the fact the composition of a non-invertible bases along two invertible cells are somewhat elementary operations while the term transitive refers to the fact the composition of three invertible cells are reminiscent of a terminary transitive property if one sees $\infty$-groupoids as generalisations of the notion of equivalence relation.
|
$\to$ |
The goal of this section is to use the kappa and tau constructions -- which may be seen as source and target maps between different types of gluing of discs -- to define dimensionally coherent composition of cells.
On the one hand, normal spinal coheroids will permit the composition of three cells in the form of a whiskering (or cylinder of discs) where the middle cell (or base of the cylinder) should be regarded as non-reversible and where the whiskers (are sides of the cylinder) should be regarded as reversible. The term normal refers to the fact that the composition of a non-reversible cell along two others is what one would like to think as an elementary operation (in contrast to the next type of operation). On the other hand, transitive spinal coheroids will permit the composition of three cells in the form of a whiskering (or cylinder of discs) where all the cells are considered reversible. The term transitive now refers to the fact that the composition of three reversible cells is reminiscent of a transitive property if one sees $\infty$-groupoids as generalisations of the notion of equivalence relation. |
Ch. 6 ; page 299 ; sec. 6.3.3 ; l. 2
|
under the interesting pushouts
|
$\to$ |
under certain pushouts
|
Ch. 6 ; page 335 ; l.-12
|
By copying the reasoning in which the category of Grothendieck's $\infty$-groupoids have been equipped with a spinal category structure, one may show that the free cocompletion $C^{_{\triangledown}} \cong \mathbf{Psh}(C)$ has a spinal category (see Remark 6.16). Finally, Remark 4.96 shows that if the unit of the adjunction
\[
\int^{g \in C} \nabla_g(\_) \otimes i(g) \vdash \mathbf{Top}(i(\_),\_)
\]
(defined thereof) is a componentwise weak equivalence in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$, then $\mathbf{Top}(i(\_),\_):\mathbf{Top} \to \mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$ is a covertebral equivalence, which by Proposition 1.47 and Proposition 4.95, would prove the Homotopy Hypothesis.
|
$\to$ |
Then, by copying our previous reasoning by which every category of Grothendieck's $\infty$-groupoids has been equipped with a spinal category structure, one may show that the free cocompletion $C^{_{\triangledown}} = \mathbf{Psh}(C)$ has a spinal category structure too (see Remark 6.16). Finally, we could try to conclude by using Remark 4.96, which requires us to show that the unit of the adjunction
\begin{align}
\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!\!(6.68) \quad \quad \quad \quad \quad & \int^{g \in C} \nabla_g(\_) \otimes i(g) \vdash \mathbf{Top}(i(\_),\_)\\
\end{align}
(defined thereof) is a componentwise weak equivalence in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$. This would imply that the functor $\mathbf{Top}(i(\_),\_):\mathbf{Top} \to \mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$ is a covertebral equivalence, which by Proposition 1.48 and Proposition 4.95, would prove the Homotopy Hypothesis. But this argument happens to fail in some cases and therefore needs to be refined. Indeed, it simply suffices to notice that the argument does not work for strict groupoids. For instance, the group with two elements $\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z}=\{0,1\}$ may be seen as an obvious one-object strict $\infty$-groupoid, let us call it $B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})$, and hence a Grothendieck $\infty$-groupoid by the result of [5]. But the image of $B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})$ via the left adjoint functor of adjunction (6.68) is a terminal topological space since the relation $1+1=0$ forces any path in $B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})$ to contract to the topological realisation of the point 0.
\[
\int^{g \in C} B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})(g) \otimes i(g) = \{0\}
\]
We thus conclude that the unit of adjunction (6.68) at the Grothendieck $\infty$-groupoid $B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})$ is the canonical map $!:B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z}) \to \mathbf{1}$, which is far from being a weak equivalence in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$. Instead, we should rather seek to prove the following property: For every object $X:C^{\mathrm{op}} \to \mathbf{Set}$ in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$ for which there exists a topological space $Y$ and a morphisms $f:X(\_) \Rightarrow \mathbf{Top}(i(\_),Y)$ in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$, the unit of (6.68) at the object $X$ is a weak equivalence in $\mathbf{Mod}(C^{\mathrm{op}})$. At least, this property does not hold for the Grothendieck $\infty$-groupoid $B(\mathbb{Z}/2\mathbb{Z})$, since it is too strict for being mapped to an image of $\mathbf{Top}(i(\_),\_)$, and it does not contradict Quillen's criteria for Quillen equivalences (see Proposition 1.48).
|